今日看料

The Subject in Palanka: “The Philosophy of Parochialism” and the Work of Immanent Critique

This is part of a roundtable, Serbian Philosopher Radomir Konstantinovi膰: 鈥淧arochialism鈥 in Translation.

If today the subject is vanishing, aphorisms take upon themselves the duty “to consider the evanescent itself as essential.” They insist, in opposition to Hegel鈥檚 practice and yet in accordance with his thought, on negativity.

鈥擳heodor W. Adorno in Minima Moralia

 

The vanishing (philosophical) subject, whose self-destruction under the prevailing conditions of modernity is the core concern of Radomir Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 Filosofija palanke (1969), makes a barely perceptible appearance in the famous first line of this most idiosyncratic work of Yugoslav philosophy: Iskustvo nam je palana膷ko, or in English, 鈥渙ur experience is parochial.鈥[1] This pithy, seemingly categorical statement in Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 native Serbo-Croatian, the language known today as BCMS (Bosnian- Croatian-Montenegrin-Serbian), is quite unlike any other in the volume. Some of the ways it differs from the rest of the text are apparent in translation. Standing apart from the first full paragraph of the book, the sentence appears on the opening page of The Philosophy of Parochialism (translation by Ljiljana Nikoli膰 and Branislav Jakovljevi膰 2021) as an epigraph of sorts, an assertion seemingly borrowed from another source or made in someone else鈥檚 voice. Its simplicity is also at odds with Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 far more elaborate philosophical idiom, a style so severe鈥攖o borrow Gillian Rose鈥檚 term for the style of Hegel鈥檚 Philosophy of Right鈥攖hat it intentionally pushes even the highly-inflected original language to its breaking point, making no concessions to the reader, and, more importantly, resulting in a kind of prose from which it is difficult to extract anything resembling an aphorism.[2]

It is thus significant that the author who thinks in paragraphs and who aspires to a style difficult to cite begins his work with a proposition that both functions as a citation and readily lends itself to becoming one.[3] And that is indeed what 鈥渋skustvo nam je palana膷ko鈥 has become: a perfunctory quote whose declarative nature is somehow self-evident even to readers who agree on little else about the book. The copula (鈥渋s鈥) joins a fixed grammatical subject (鈥渙ur experience鈥) with a contingent grammatical predicate (鈥減arochial鈥), establishing a relation of identity or equivalence between the two terms and giving this ordinary proposition its unmistakable meaning. And yet there is more鈥攁 lot more鈥攖o this sentence than meets the eye. As I will show by the end of the article, a twist in the grammatical subject, one that involves the possessive dative case in Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 original formulation, calls into question the seemingly inescapable law of identity in the exact proposition in which it is affirmed. In other words, the archaic possessive dative allows Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 programmatic proposition to be read 鈥渟peculatively,鈥 as Rose would put it, so that the subject of this proposition, 鈥渙ur experience,鈥 can acquire a new meaning by wresting another kind of experience from the parochial conditions that preclude it.[4]

Interpreting Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 opening sentence gets even more complicated when one realizes that this statement never had a future in which it would not function as an aphorism. Konstantinovi膰 appears to have anticipated as much: it is at times 鈥渄angerous鈥 and 鈥減unishable,鈥 he writes in the very next sentence, 鈥渢o whisper this into the ear of parochial arrogance鈥 (25/7). While the warning ends here鈥攁nd appears to point squarely to the well-known perils faced by critical social philosophy since the time of Socrates鈥攖he compound sentence that contains the warning spills into the next clause: 鈥渟ometimes, however, this word stretches right to the concept of predestination [pojma sudbinskog]: the palanka is, as they say, our fate, our lot in life.鈥 Two distinct outcomes (in two parallel clauses) are set apart here by the disjunctive adverb. Suggesting that our experience is parochial may sometimes (ponekad) expose the critic to some ominous fate; 鈥渁t [other] times, however鈥 (ponekad, medjutim), the same opening sentence and its predicate may lead to a new realization about the nature of totality as a self-identical and unchanging whole. The latter is only the first of many fleeting definitions of palanka in Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 work. In this particular articulation, palanka, a historically-produced phenomenon for Konstantinovi膰, is theorized in terms of its compulsion to eternalize itself in response to what it perceives as its belatedness. Making a virtue of necessity, palanka ensures that there is no future different from its present, and this ruse becomes one manifestation of the process by which everything is made identical or commensurable. Exactly how this insight is produced from within the confines of the same dangerous proposition is the topic of what follows. If true, however, this new realization about the power of total identity makes the propositional identity-affirming form of Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 opening statement necessary. The sentence was condemned all along to the only meaning it could have in the propositional form it had to take, and in which, as we shall see, it could not be entirely understood. There is no escaping the machinations of identity鈥攏ot in logic and not in language鈥攁nd this seems to be the meaning of the peril Konstantinovi膰 flagged at the outset.

To understand the exact danger Konstantinovi膰 warns against is to understand the depth of the distinctly modern challenge confronting any genuinely critical analysis. The danger is not that of (reason) daring to speak truth to power, as we may be inclined to conclude, but of having no means鈥攃onceptual or linguistic鈥攁nd no independent standpoint from which to mount a critique of total power, the exercise of which has itself become rational. The danger is methodological in nature and involves the problem of transcending (in the age of non-transcendence) the immanence of identity.[5] One cannot just will oneself out of the world, logic, and language, which are themselves built on the semblance of identity. Whether this semblance is a function of thinking itself or a historical manifestation of the logic of equivalence and exchange, it is still a binding category, our 鈥渟econd nature,鈥 determining the limits of what can be said, thought, or done.[6] To put it simply, one can speak of the experiential content of palanka only in the language of palanka鈥攐r not at all. This presents a problem for the critic averse to these limitations, a critic who wishes for a world beyond palanka. Whence comes the knowledge of another kind of experience? From what perspective within the binding appearance of total identity could a critic possibly discern traces of difference?

No such perspective exists outside of palanka. Positing the existence of difference in some realm beyond 辫补濒补苍办补鈥檚 physical and conceptual palisades is, according to Konstantinovi膰, a defining feature of parochial reason and thus not a viable methodological alternative鈥攅ven if it is one widely shared by traditional metaphysicians and their critics alike. For the later, for instance, difference may reside in the ecstatic essence of Dasein, in the arbitrary nature of language, in the interstitial space of hybridity and ambiguity, or in other equally abstract receptacles in which difference is supposedly spared the ravages of history. Such hypostasizing of difference may even be the most significant expression of parochial reason because it best captures the process and logic of deception (na膷别濒辞 prevara) that permeates all other principles. According to this logic, palanka is constituted through more than just a series of deceits it carries out itself. For palanka to come into existence, its own work of deception must also be externalized so that deceit suddenly confronts palanka as an objective force, one that is not of its own making and that threatens palanka from without.

As a technique of agitation, deceit is a common analytic in studies of fascism. So is the importance of the constitutive other to the creation of the self. But if this was all Konstantinovi膰 had in mind with his repeated discussions of deceit as the logic of palanka, The Philosophy of Parochialism would be little more than a positivist study of an aberration鈥攕ay, a paranoid style in certain politics鈥攐ne that could be avoided in the future by making the gullible a little less susceptible to the charms of fascism. I think that Konstantinovi膰 has something far more insidious in mind. Something more akin to the fragmentation of human experience produced by the phenomenon of reification: in a world enchanted anew, history reverts to nature, and the activity of the historical subject is once again relegated to that of passive observance of social forces and of reality as given.[7] In this respect, deceit is the form in which the unfinished project of modernity is experienced. One knows one has descended into the realm of palanka when one discovers reason sheltering from itself in the indolence (lenjost) it attributes to hostile fate.

But how does one detect deceit when the hell of palanka, to paraphrase Walter Benjamin, is not 鈥渟ome place that awaits us鈥 in the Balkan semi-periphery but 鈥渢his life here and now鈥?[8] The recent resurgence of nativism across Europe and in the Americas makes it perhaps easier to grasp that fascism, according to Konstantinovi膰, is always a homegrown phenomenon regardless of where it springs up. The soil it grows in is the so-called liberal or bourgeois society and the abandoned work of universal freedom. No one place or culture is condemned to it鈥攐r spared from it鈥攂y virtue of some trait supposedly intrinsic to it. And I say this and point to the spirit of palanka in our own midst in the 鈥淲est鈥 not to exonerate or minimize its sway in the 鈥淓ast,鈥 i.e., under the cultural and political conditions in which Konstantinovi膰 first detected it. In fact, Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 ethno-nationalist critics at home seldom fail to add more empirical evidence to his original claim that 鈥淪erbian Nazism鈥 is very much a homegrown phenomenon, not an imported one.[9] Branislav Jakovljevi膰 makes a similar point in his introduction to the work we are discussing in this roundtable: Konstantinovi膰 is interested less in various manifestations of totalitarianism than he is in 鈥渋nvestigating their source, which appears to be divorced from particular historical events and is, at the same time, their basic condition鈥 (鈥淭he Drone of Dialectics,鈥 2-3). Under this view, Nazism is not an exception but 鈥渢he most radical expression of bourgeois rationality鈥 (ibid., 9).

One way to proceed without ignoring the severity of the problem or giving in to its immensity is through a methodological approach that in the left-Hegelian intellectual tradition goes by the name of immanent critique; arguably, this critical methodological stance is even older, epitomized already in Giambattista Vico鈥檚 poetic philosophy and his verum-factum principle: one can always know the truth in what one makes. Unlike the external standpoint posited in conventional or transcendental criticism, to use Theodor Adorno鈥檚 well-known distinction, immanent critique moves from within the object of its analysis, measuring it according to its own principles, its own reason.[10] Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 critique, immersed in the appearance of total identity as it must be, cultivates no escapist fantasies at a methodological level. This would be an act of pure ideology since, as I suggested above, one cannot hypostatize difference or change at the methodological level of a philosophical investigation and hope to arrive at anything but empty abstractions that ultimately absorb all difference and prevent any change. There is virtually no way out of the palanka, and this realization鈥攏either a literary contrivance nor the confession of a mind resigned to its lot in life鈥攊s instead a sign of reason doing the one thing that it can and must do: canceling or negating itself so that actual emancipatory struggles can be fought in history instead of theory.

The only genuinely critical perspective lies within palanka and it allows Konstantinovi膰 to break through the untruth of the self-producing social totality by means of its own measure鈥攙ia the principle of identity. Every one of the fundamental principles through which palanka is constituted as a totality is shown to be contradictory: for instance, insularity turns out to be predicated on world-making; indolence requires exertion; transparency acts as a screen; determinism results in arbitrariness; na茂ve realism is mediated by symbols; and naivete itself, in a particularly effective turn of phrase, achieves its purest expression in its 鈥渞ejection of naivete [found in] children and poets, lovers and saints鈥 (151/169).[11] The reader may get a sense of how Konstantinovi膰 moves through contradictions in the following excerpt from The Philosophy of Parochialism:

The necessity, forced onto [the subject] by his strictly determined world, seems to be shattered precisely by what constitutes it, the absolute determinateness. [鈥 I am [or I exist] only in one definite way of a strictly defined world, and therefore I am not, i.e., every one of my ways [of being] is not mine and, therefore, is a way not necessary for me. In this attitude about necessity, the parochial spirit鈥檚 determinism is essentially self-contradictory; the principle of arbitrariness, as the expression of this non-necessity, [鈥 is inevitably established and so is thereby also the principle of replaceability: if a real change is impossible (the world is finished, complete, once and forever preordained by a will that negates our own), then any change is possible; that is to say, any attitude is replaceable by the very fact that this attitude is wholly deceptive because it is irrelevant. (43/30-31)

Taken seriously and judged by its own standards, 辫补濒补苍办补鈥檚 claim to total identity is shown to be false. It is untrue both because it is mired in conceptual contradictions and because it falls short of approximating the actual totality, an idea Konstantinovi膰 very much retains.[12] I will focus on contradictions, but the latter point is also important to bear in mind. The Philosophy of Parochialism is not a critique of totality but of its semblance. It is a critique of whatever deceptive abstraction passes for totality by excluding more than it can admit. And what it excludes above everything else, what it must exclude to maintain its hold, is the activity of the subject even if that subject is merely an object of history, a vanishing subject with no experience of his or her own. In the age when most critics have learned to habitually recoil from the term totality鈥攊n part because of its nominal association with 鈥渢otalitarianism鈥濃擨 find it in fact useful to think of palanka as a concept that replaces the ideologically-laden term 鈥渢otalitarianism,鈥 making 鈥渢otality鈥 an operative concept again and allowing for a more critical analysis of political reaction.

Not only does immanent critique not posit difference, it also discovers none in the process of showing how palanka is constituted of contradictions. Nonidentity is here an effect of immanent critique, not a trace of some difference that survives within the false totality of palanka. Again, there is no heterogeneity here that does not express itself as a contradiction, no difference that is not mediated by identity. This is important because immanent critique is not an attempt to tell an untold story or let some subaltern speak of a miraculous feat of survival from a catastrophe that is both total and yet not all-encompassing. Only parochial reason can maintain such contradictions (in the form of antinomies). Nor are we dealing here with Ideologiekritik in the narrowest sense. The task ahead of critical philosophy entails so much more than exposing deception or lifting the veil of appearances. No reality hides behind such veils as long as it does not include an active subject鈥攁nd the subject is not a 鈥渢hing鈥 to be discovered in the course of a critique. Or, in Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 own words, 辫补濒补苍办补鈥檚 is a life on stage, 鈥渁n actor鈥檚 life, with masks, but without real faces behind them鈥 (44/31). Immanent critique is after a different kind of truth鈥攁 social truth implicit in the failure of parochial reason.

One part of this truth points to the coercive means by which palanka is held together. This, in turn, allows us to understand why no historical manifestation of palanka has ever collapsed under the weight of its own contradictions. Philosophy cannot bring an end to palanka. Only social and political practice can do that. But neither will palanka collapse without critical philosophy exposing as false the purely conceptual reconciliation of these contradictions. The other part of the social truth produced by immanent critique involves reason or the subject reasserting itself in a realm from which it has long been banished. Immanent critique鈥檚 determinate negations push through the bounds of parochial reason, past the limits it placed on the experience and knowledge of a reality less impoverished, illusory, and unfree than the one immediately given to palanka. Reason knows not what lies on the other side, and as long as it does not give in to the temptation to imagine that other world, it can be certain of its existence and perhaps even of its own ultimate triumph over the semblance that is palanka. How? There are two possible explanations for this overcoming of restrictions intrinsic to the idea of palanka. Both explanations will appear dynamic, but only the latter is transformative and dialectical.

Having just witnessed its ability to generate contradictions and render palanka鈥檚 claim to total identity false, reason may be tempted to ground its newly demonstrated power in the process of negation itself. The content of the actual contradictions will then recede in importance in comparison to reason鈥檚 rediscovery of its own dynamic nature as a formal and inalienable property. Experience here becomes a function of some abstract capacity, an ontological ground that always-already defines the ontic or empirical subject while remaining independent of it and, as importantly, independent of the object of experience. The active dimension belongs to this new subject as some fundamental quality or mechanism, and not as something the subject produces through conceptualization or labor.[13] The influence of literary and philosophical existentialism on Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 thought鈥攁long with an overall tendency in today鈥檚 criticism to view existentialism through the lens of its most conservative adherents鈥攎akes it possible that this process-oriented explanation of a reinvigorated intellectual experience is indeed the one Konstantinovi膰 endorsed.

I believe that the more plausible explanation involves reason awakening from the dream it had of itself by recognizing its own work in the object鈥攁nd not the process鈥攐f its analysis. Immanent critique wrests truth from semblance by isolating active elements in 辫补濒补苍办补鈥檚 inert nature. If the object can be shown to contain the evidence of social and historical labor that goes into maintaining its integrity, then immanent critique can render that object not only knowable in the Vichian sense I mentioned above, but also subject to change. To realize that the objective world is but the objectification of the subject鈥攁nd thus not engendered by some transcendental force or a realm of necessity independent of the subject鈥攁llows that same alienated subject to alter the object by altering herself in history.

The subject capable of experiencing, knowing, and changing the world she has made unchangeable is the absent telos of Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 study. He cannot posit the subject鈥檚 existence any more than he can deliver it to the reader in the form of a definitive conclusion. Taking Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 word for it鈥攐r, worse, taking my word for it鈥攚ould return the reader to the gates of 辫补濒补苍办补鈥檚 intractable reality. One has to instead produce intellectual experience anew by witnessing this active subject come into existence not only on the pages of The Philosophy of Parochialism, but in one鈥檚 own thought. Reading Konstantinovi膰 is necessary but it is not in itself sufficient. Or, to put it more bluntly, the experience Konstantinovi膰 seeks to create in his readers and interlocutors is not the experience of internalizing, emulating, or citing any one of his revelations (in this respect, the habit of referring to Filosofija palanke as a sacred text by Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 liberal readers at home is quite unfortunate). The point, instead, is to think alongside Konstantinovi膰 in order to break free of our own parochial experience.[14]

Those reading Konstantinovi膰 in the original may have a slight advantage over other readers when it comes to recognizing the subjective force in the objective form that surrounds them. If they listen carefully, they may hear in the first 鈥渨hispered鈥 sentence of the book the barely detectable sound of an absent (philosophical) subject making her presence known within the exact proposition that establishes that no such thing is possible. As I indicated at the outset, the relation of possession in the grammatical subject of the first sentence (鈥渙ur experience鈥 or 鈥iskustvo nam鈥 in Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 original phrase) is expressed with a possessive dative construction (the clitic 鈥nam鈥 or, roughly, 鈥渢o us鈥) instead of the more standard possessive pronoun (na拧别 or our). The use of the possessive dative is not unusual in Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 native language and it does not, in this case, affect the conventional meaning of the phrase. The practice is considered archaic, however, and a reader thinking about the formal features of this phrase will certainly sense a folksier register in use. In fact, between the title of the book and its first two sentences, Konstantinovi膰 employs three archaic formulations. Along with nominalization, archaisms are the most obvious linguistic expression of 辫补濒补苍办补鈥檚 resistance to temporalization and it is thus likely that the possessive dative is simply an example of immanent critique not ignoring the language of palanka as it attempts to break through it.[15] But I think there is more to it.

The archaic possessive dative also creates the effect of a nascent speculative proposition within the ordinary identity-affirming one. If Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 first sentence had an indirect object, it would be inflected the same way and the meaning of the proposition would change from 鈥渙ur experience is parochial鈥 to 鈥渆xperience is (made) parochial to us.鈥 What we think is inalienably ours and what largely constitutes us as subjects, i.e., our experience, turns out to be a function performed by someone or something else鈥攂y palanka. In other words, palanka experiences our own experience for us. Our experience is an object in this proposition, palanka is its logical subject, and we are reduced to passive recipients of an act we were supposed to be capable of. This is the grim reality of 鈥渓iving鈥 in palanka until we catch, within the illusion of having our own existence, a glimpse of recognition that 鈥渙ur鈥 experience has been stolen from us, expropriated by a force that is social and historical, rather than natural. This recognition is what makes experience possible and thus invalidates the claim that 鈥渙ur experience is parochial.鈥 The way out of palanka goes through it. Konstantinovi膰 saw this clearly in part because he had no illusions about his own parochial reality. Rereading Konstantinovi膰 now in the 鈥淲est鈥 and in the new English translation, I am realizing that not only have we given up on the methodological work of immanent critique, we also largely lack the insight鈥攐r is it moral courage?鈥攖o even admit that palanka is within us.

 

Djordje Popovi膰 is Assistant Professor of South Slavic Studies in the Department of Slavic Languages and Literatures at UC Berkeley, where he is also affiliated with the Program in Critical Theory. He specializes in twentieth- and twenty-first-century South Slavic literature and culture, comparative and transnational literature, and the Frankfurt School of critical theory. His essays on the appropriation of the dialectical tradition and on the ontologizing of alienation in the Western reception of East European modernism have appeared in the journals Contradictions, Critical Quarterly and Qui Parle, and in an edited volume, History, Imperialism, Critique: New Essays in World Literature (Routledge, 2019).

[1] Radomir Konstantinovi膰, The Philosophy of Parochialism (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2021), 25; Radomir Konstantinovi膰, Filosofija palanke (Belgrade: Nolit, 1991), 7. Hereafter cited parenthetically in the text with the first page number referring to the English translation and the second number referring to the 1991 Nolit edition.

[2] On writing political theory in the 鈥渟evere鈥 style, see Gillian Rose, Hegel Contra Sociology (Brooklyn, NY: Verso, 2009), esp. 54-55, 156-157.

[3] For Konstantinovi膰, Samuel Beckett鈥檚 novel Molloy (1951) was an important literary model of a work irreducible to any one line: 鈥淗ere is an author whom you absolutely cannot cite,鈥 Konstantinovi膰 declared in the afterword to the 1959 Serbo-Croatian translation of the novel; some 40 years later, Konstantinovi膰 returned to this assessment in his final work, Beket: prijatelj (Belgrade: Otkrovenje, 2000), 84 (trans. mine).

[4] Rose, Hegel Contra Sociology, 52.

[5] On 鈥榯ranscending without transcendence,鈥 see Ernst Bloch, The Principle of Hope, Vol. 3 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986), 1373.

[6]听 On the Hegelian term 鈥渟econd nature,鈥 see Georg Luk谩cs, The Theory of the Novel (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1971), 62-65.

[7] I am drawing here on Georg Luk谩cs鈥檚 classic definition from his 1923 essay 鈥淩eification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat.鈥 See Luk谩cs, History and Class Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1923), 83-222.

[8] 鈥淗ell,鈥 for Benjamin, 鈥渋s not something that awaits us, but this life here and now.鈥 See Walter Benjamin, The Arcades Project (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002), 473.

[9] For one contemporary example of 鈥淪erbian Nazism鈥 flaunted in response to Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 work, see the genesis of the BCMS phrase slu膷ajni Srbi (accidental Serbs).

[10] See Theodor W. Adorno, 鈥淐ultural Criticism and Society,鈥 Prisms (MIT Press, 1981), 17-34. The original articulation is Hegel鈥檚. See Hegel, The Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 53-55.

[11] If a single passage could encapsulate Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 argument, then it might be the following one: 鈥The parochial spirit finds its greatest deception in the fear of deception, just as the greatest naivete of this spirit is its rejection of naivete. It is [鈥 na茂ve because it isn鈥檛 na茂ve. It really does not know the naivete of children and poets, lovers and saints, though whom existence speaks up most profoundly precisely owing to their naivete, capable of receiving the totality of that existence that cannot be accepted by the limited (and limiting) sprit of the attainable-real or the verifiably-meaningful鈥 (151/169).

[12] For one example of Konstantinovi膰鈥檚 use of 鈥渢otality,鈥 see the quote in the footnote above.

[13] This particular approach to 鈥渙vercoming鈥 the shortfalls of modernity has become a signature move in what Pierre Bourdieu aptly called the 鈥渃onservative revolution鈥 in philosophy. See Pierre Bourdieu, The Political Ontology of Martin Heidegger (Stanford University Press, 1991), 62鈥63.

[14] For a similar heuristic recommendation on how to allow intellectual experience to spring forth from the language which precludes it, see Adorno, 鈥淪koteinos, or How to Read Hegel鈥 (Hegel: Three Studies (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), 89-148, esp. 138-139.

[15] On nominalization and 辫补濒补苍办补鈥檚 attempt to 鈥渆stablish a language that is based on nouns,鈥 see Jakovljevi膰, 3.

 

References

Adorno, Theodor W. 鈥淐ultural Criticism and Society.鈥 In Prisms, 17-34. Translated by Samuel Weber and Shierry Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981.

—. 鈥淪koteinos, or How to Read Hegel.鈥 In Hegel: Three Studies, 89-148. Translated by Shierry Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1963.

Benjamin, Walter. The Arcades Project. Translated by Howard Eiland and Kevin McLaughlin. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999.

Bloch, Ernst. The Principle of Hope, Volume Three. Translated by Neville Plaice et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986.

Bourdieu, Pierre. The Political Ontology of Martin Heidegger. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1991.

Hegel, Georg. The Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by Arnold Vincent Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.

Jakovljevi膰, Branislav. 鈥淭he Drone of Dialectics: On Parochialism and Deprovincialization.鈥 Introduction to The Philosophy of Parochialism by Radomir Konstantinovi膰, 1-21. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2021.

Konstantinovi膰, Radomir. Beket: prijatelj. Belgrade: Otkrovenje, 2000.

—. Filosofija palanke. Belgrade: Nolit, 1991.

—. The Philosophy of Parochialism. Translated by Branislav Jakovljevi膰 and Ljiljana Nikoli膰. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2021.

Luk谩cs, Georg. 鈥淩eification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat鈥 In History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, 83-222. Translated by Rodney Livingstone. Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1990.

—. The Theory of the Novel. Translated by Anna Bostock. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1971.

Rose, Gillian. Hegel Contra Sociology. Brooklyn, NY: Verso, 2009.

 

Published on February 15, 2024.

 

 

 

 

Share:

Print Friendly, PDF & Email