This is part of a roundtable on Marc Cr茅pon鈥檚 Murderous Consent: On the Accommodation of Violent Death.
Murderous Consent鈥檚 aim is, first, to critique political violence, whether hegemonic or revolutionary. The book鈥檚 aim is, second, to enunciate another politics that never legitimizes violence in any form. These aims could not be more profound, attempting, as they do, to overturn both Western political theory and contemporary geopolitical practice.
But those of us who take such aims seriously have more to learn from how Murderous Consent goes astray than from where it arrives. The antithesis of political violence does not lie in the directions Cr茅pon thinks, least of all humanitarianism or cosmopolitanism. Though these orientations presume to interrupt Western politics, each is in fact continuous with it; though they claim to oppose geopolitical violence, their very possibility presupposes it. In short, Cr茅pon鈥檚 work extends the Western political tradition鈥檚 elevation of security above all other values. More rigorous philosophies of nonviolence disavow this principle altogether.
鈥淢urderous consent鈥 names the tacit acceptance of violent death. Cr茅pon argues that people in rich countries consent to murder whenever they say or do nothing to oppose famine, absent health care, and civil war elsewhere鈥攅ven as they witness the overproduction of food, accumulation of pharmaceutical profit, and enrichment of weapons manufacturers in their own countries.[1] As Martel observes in Murderous Consent鈥檚 foreword, Cr茅pon鈥檚 pejorative use of 鈥渃onsent鈥 critiques the liberal tradition. Though its commitment to popular consent validates this tradition, such consent effectively endorses the violence governments commit: 鈥渂y rendering [consent] murderous[,] Cr茅pon is subverting the entire [liberal] political apparatus.鈥[2]
The authors Cr茅pon studies supposedly trace 鈥渁 path that extirpates humanity from the endless spiral of murderous consent鈥 (93). Following this path, Cr茅pon intends to articulate a 鈥減rinciple of politics鈥 that 鈥渟eeks only life and not death,鈥 an intention inspired by Camus (xiii, 80, 82, 163). Unlike his contemporaries, Camus opposed both colonial andrevolutionary violence. He understood colonial torture and anticolonial terrorism to mirror each other, the FLN-bombing of settlers no less immoral than French counterinsurgency techniques. In Cr茅pon鈥檚 view, Camus鈥檚 desire to shatter the torture-terrorism dyad makes his work newly relevant post-9/11, when the vicious circle of state and non-state violence defines geopolitics again. Cr茅pon thus poses Camus鈥檚 question once more: how do we oppose political violence without resorting to such violence ourselves?
Cr茅pon鈥檚 answer is, in short, that cosmopolitanism must replace identitarianism. Political resistance should unify all people rather than separating them into 鈥減redetermined forms of community鈥 (32, 92). The basis of such unity is human vulnerability.
Here, Cr茅pon appears to follow Judith Butler, as Martel insists (xii). And, indeed, Butler鈥檚 Frames of War asserts that nonviolence presupposes understanding injurable life as a general condition.[3] Cr茅pon declares, repeatedly, that politics, understood properly, responds to the other鈥檚 vulnerability: 鈥渁ny relationship, moral or political, 鈥 heed[s] the appeal of the other for attention, care, and help鈥 (5).
But, curiously, Cr茅pon reduces 鈥渧ulnerability鈥 to 鈥渕ortality,鈥 almost always presenting the two together. The latter effectively subsumes the former鈥攁s if unnatural death were the only, or always the worst, form of human suffering. He insists, without elaboration: 鈥渢he most radical and daunting form of 鈥 vulnerability is the other鈥檚 mortality鈥 (11). We fulfill our responsibility to the other, therefore, when protect them from such death. The effect of reducing vulnerability to mortality and ethical responsibility to caring for those threatened with death is to collapse all political violence into killing (active or passive)鈥攔emarkably, the only injustice to which Murderous Consent ever objects.
Excluding every other form of deprivation from the category of violence enables Cr茅pon to make humanitarianism鈥斺渇eeding the hungry, giving drink to the thirsty, assisting the afflicted,鈥 and providing 鈥渕edical relief鈥 to the infirm鈥攖he antithesis of violence, as he does throughout (31,聽 160). In his view, humanitarian 鈥渋nterventions鈥 and 鈥渆mergency aid鈥 oppose murderous consent (6). Even more pointedly, he extols 鈥渢he world鈥檚 nongovernmental organizations鈥 as examples of ethical responsibility (111).
But the reality of NGOs demonstrates the fallacy of Cr茅pon鈥檚 claims. Even as NGOs do, of course, save lives, they are, far from the antithesis of political violence, irreversibly entangled in it. Humanitarian interventions avert catastrophe by keeping people at risk of dying barely above the threshold of life. Once mortality falls below the level that arbitrarily defines 鈥渃atastrophe,鈥 the often-slow violence that precipitated the catastrophe becomes invisible once more鈥攁nd hence can continue ad infinitum. Those who never cross over that threshold remain 鈥渙ut of focus,鈥 enduring indefinite deprivation.[4] This dynamic is one-way NGOs, far from opposing political violence, facilitate it: their fixation on mortality draws global attention away from every other form of distress.
But it is only one way. Often becoming quasi-permanent, NGO-rule runs 鈥渞oughshod over local communities 鈥 in the name of the higher good鈥: namely, saving those threatened with death.[5] From a humanitarian perspective, this higher good, this 鈥渓aw external to and superior to law,鈥 is more important than redressing social and economic inequality or even defending democracy and thus obscures the political forces that cause catastrophe.[6] Cr茅pon鈥檚 own concept of morality, oriented always toward those at risk of death rather than systemic critique and transformation, reflects these principles precisely.
In regard to Cr茅pon鈥檚 claim that 鈥渕edical relief鈥 exemplifies opposition to murderous consent, we should note that M茅decins Sans Fronti猫res co-founder Bernard Kouchner became a leading proponent of 鈥渢he right to intervene.鈥 He argued that international institutions can ignore state sovereignty when humanitarian law has been violated. Hence, though it opposes murderous consent in Cr茅pon鈥檚 precise terms, medical relief鈥攍ike humanitarian intervention in general鈥攔equires armed support. NGOs cannot intervene in the ways Cr茅pon lists without military backing. Conversely, any military action today appears excessive unless, conversely, it articulates a humanitarian rationale. As Fassin and Pandolfi have observed, 鈥渢he two sides come together on the same scene, in a reciprocal 鈥 dependency鈥攖he military increasingly calling on humanitarians to legitimize their interventions and the latter needing the former to ensure their safety鈥 (11).
Military interventions that claim to save life become legitimate on these grounds鈥攅ven when, as in the case of both the NATO bombing of Yugoslavia and the US invasion of Iraq, they violate international law. Fassin and Pandolfi have argued that, in contemporary international relations, 鈥渉umanitarian鈥 intervention has replaced 鈥渏ust war鈥 (13). I would suggest instead that in the postcolonial era鈥攚hen Western violence in the non-Western world became unjust for the first time鈥攈umanitarianism has made it widely acceptable again. Humanitarian intervention is still, Fassin and Pandolfi emphasize, the 鈥渓aw of the strongest鈥攖his is what makes it possible.鈥 It is the most pervasive neocolonial paradigm today.
The years after WWII and, in particular, the Cold War have been marked by an ever- increasing number of NGOs. The latter decades have been distinguished as well by proliferating emergencies around the world. One could argue, as this chronology suggests, that NGOs engender emergencies, not the reverse. Whereas Schmitt famously declared, in the early twentieth century, that 鈥渟overeign is the one who decides the exception,鈥 Adi Ophir has observed, a century later, that sovereigns no longer monopolize this decision (71, 75). States of exception take the form, increasingly, of 鈥渉umanitarian emergencies,鈥 whose existence only NGOs are qualified to declare and whose chaotic conditions they alone are competent to govern.
Humanitarianism is itself, therefore, now sovereign. It developed alongside the late eighteenth century鈥檚 democratic revolutions and, as Arendt鈥檚 Origins of Totalitarianism and On Revolution argue, immediately co-opted them.[7] From this moment forward, the 鈥渉umane鈥濃攊.e., the protection of life鈥攈as justified the suspension of democracy whenever necessary. Gandhi considered the humanitarian commitment to 鈥渓ife as an absolute value鈥 as responsible for the 鈥渕assive scale of modern warfare鈥 as Nazism was.[8] He wrote: 鈥渢he West attaches an exaggerated importance to prolonging man鈥檚 earthly existence. 鈥 I do not want that excessive desire of living 鈥 at the cost of tenderness for subhuman life鈥.[9] In Gandhi鈥檚 view, 鈥淸o]nly by giving up the thirst for life 鈥 represented in modern war and medicine alike 鈥 could the urge to kill be tamed.鈥[10]
Cr茅pon tolerates the sovereign鈥檚 right to take life and to let die, merely ameliorating it with humanitarian interventions, an absolutely necessary aspect (the other side, we could say) of violent death. Fassin and Pandolfi again: 鈥渂oth military and humanitarian actors 鈥 reject the sovereignty of states in the name of a higher moral order, and both are thus similarly engaged with extralegality and extraterritoriality; 鈥渋n structural terms, military and humanitarian actors place themselves under the same law of exception鈥 (15). Cr茅pon thus silently colludes with the structural violence he so passionately condemns.
Though he insists that to oppose murderous consent, we must first 鈥渄isrup[t] the geography[,] history[,] politics, and 鈥 economics that nourish and orchestrate killing,鈥 he does not explore this geography, history, et cetera to any extent at all (3). Relying on a Freudian (and, to a lesser extent, Levinasian) theory of violence, Cr茅pon鈥檚 discussions of the topic are, instead, completely ahistorical. According to Freud, the desire to murder is primordial, an 鈥渁ncestral temptation,鈥 the 鈥渕ost profound essence of man鈥 (9, 50, 59, 65). Even modern war, therefore, has 鈥渂iological roots鈥 (72). It unleashes 鈥渢he primitive human鈥濃攊.e., the 鈥渢aste for murder鈥鈥攆ettered inside us and 鈥渃onsigns 鈥渢he later deposits of civilization鈥 to oblivion鈥 (66). If political violence is atavistic, its antidote must progressivist. Hence, in Freud鈥檚 thought as in Cr茅pon鈥檚, the antidote involves supranational institutions that circumscribe violence not despite but precisely because they possess 鈥渃oercive power鈥 and 鈥渇orce of arms鈥 (67). Exactly like the superego, 鈥渃ivilizational progress鈥 turns humanity鈥檚 aggressive tendencies 鈥渁gainst themselves鈥 (73). The logic here is not only racist鈥攑referring 鈥渃ivilized鈥 to 鈥減rimitive鈥 humanity鈥攂ut also circular. It considers Western modernity, which has advanced political violence to previously unseen levels, the only possible defense against such violence.
Such all-too-familiar circularity is intrinsic to politics itself, which, from its ancient origins, has always claimed a singular capacity to ameliorate violent death. According to Arendt鈥檚 On Violence, 鈥渉uman mortality鈥攖he fact that men are 鈥渕ortals,鈥 as the Greeks used to say鈥攚as understood as the strongest motive for political action[,] prompt[ing] them to establish a body politic which was potentially immortal.鈥[11] Citizens feel immortal not only by virtue of their affiliation with a polity that is, in principle, permanent but also because they are less exposed to death than those without political status: 鈥減olitics was precisely a means by which to escape from the equality before death into a distinction assuring some measure of deathlessness.鈥 Murderous Consent鈥檚 aim to articulate a 鈥減rinciple of politics鈥 that 鈥渟eeks only life and not death鈥 is, therefore, tautological: this principle is indistinguishable from politics as such. In practice, it required exposing others to death. I pass, without comment, over the fact that Arendt鈥檚 disturbing account of politics鈥 origins occurs within a defense of the political sphere against those, like the Black Panthers, whose supposed violence threatened it.
Though studying politics鈥 early modern re-emergence rather than its classical roots, Foucault also emphasized its special relationship to mortality. His lectures on late sixteenth- and seventeenth-century raison d鈥櫭塼at describe it as a new 鈥渨ay of thinking鈥 immediately given the name 鈥減olitics.鈥[12] It inaugurated a temporality different from the Renaissance as well as the Middle Ages, within which the time of the state became 鈥渘ever-ending鈥 (259; recall Arendt鈥檚 description of the 鈥渂ody politic鈥 as 鈥減otentially immortal鈥). The 鈥済overnment of men鈥 had been the pastorate鈥檚 task and had aimed for their spiritual emancipation from the secular world (364, 262). By the late seventeenth century, the government of men had been appropriated by states and aspired to the salvation no longer of the soul but instead of the state itself鈥攖hat is, its preservation in perpetuity, which alone could ensure its subjects鈥 security. And the 鈥渟ecurity鈥 of early modern European populations was understood to depend, according to Foucault, on planetary 鈥渄omination, colonization, and commercial utilization鈥 (298).
Though focusing on the present, Mark Duffield has reiterated this argument. Like the early modern order, our own protects socially secure populations in the developed world by creating insecure ones elsewhere.[13] NGOs and multilateral institutions do not actually extend security to insecure populations but instead manage and contain the ubiquitous instability produced by neocolonialism and, more recently, neoliberalism. They help create 鈥渢wo worldwide typologies of human beings鈥: a minority in the Global North whose security states guarantee; the majority elsewhere that must be 鈥渟elf-sustaining,鈥 depending on the training in local empowerment practices it has received from humanitarian organizations.[14] Such organizations are one part of 鈥渁n infinite and generalized counterinsurgency strategy鈥 designed to protect the rich. Like Arendt and Foucault, Duffield suggests that politics ensures security only by exposing others to death.
Cr茅pon acknowledges that security often justifies violence. But it becomes problematic for him only when combined with sectarianism: 鈥渨henever we evoke security and identity[,] there is no vindictive discourse … we are not prepared to embrace鈥 (9). And 鈥蝉茅肠耻谤颈诲别苍迟颈迟茅鈥 (i.e., protecting one population in particular rather than humanity in general) exists in a contingent鈥攏ot necessary鈥攔elationship with politics.
In fact, Cr茅pon maintains the same commitment to security that post-WWII humanitarianism has, demanding it expand, beyond nations, to 鈥渢he global population鈥 as such. In his view, the 鈥渙bjective鈥 of politics must shift from protecting particular populations to 鈥渞esponsibility鈥 for 鈥渁ll others鈥濃攆rom the 鈥減ursuit of power, conquest, appropriation鈥 to a 鈥渟hared being-against-death [without] exception鈥 (171). On one hand, such a politics is, by definition, impossible鈥攁t least as 鈥減olitics鈥 was originally defined in Ancient Greece or redefined in early modern Europe. 鈥淭he political鈥 is defined, alternatively, by the friend-enemy distinction, Schmitt鈥檚 name for 鈥渢he most intense and extreme antagonism.鈥[15] Protecting the friend requires a willingness to kill the enemy; politics and violence are, in other words, inseparable from each other. A politics based on a shared 鈥渂eing-against-death鈥濃攖hat is, a political order without exclusion鈥攊s a contradiction in terms.
Once we recognize security to be not the antithesis of political violence but, on the contrary, its raison d鈥櫭猼re, we will discern a different tack. Embracing insecurity is the starting point for philosophies of nonviolence much more demanding than Cr茅pon鈥檚, including those of Gandhi and Simone Weil. Strangely, Cr茅pon neither cites鈥攏or demonstrates familiarity with鈥攅ither, even as he devotes his study to the ethos they made famous.
Unlike Cr茅pon鈥檚, Gandhi鈥檚 thought is diametrically opposed to the Western political tradition. From Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau to Kant, Hegel, and Mill, the origins of political society lie, as Uday Mehta has explained, in people鈥檚 鈥減rimary interest in avoiding their own death.鈥[16] Political community is associated with the desire less for freedom and justice than for security and futurity. In Hobbes, Locke, and Kant, in particular, security and futurity depend, furthermore, on the creation of colonial 鈥渇ree zones鈥 where Europeans could initiate war in the absence of any threat (145-6).
In contrast, Gandhi鈥檚 鈥渃ritique of political rationality鈥 refuses the primacy conventionally given to one鈥檚 own security and the privilege normally attributed to the future. The former leads, inevitably, to violence against those who supposedly threaten the polity, the latter, against those who supposedly hold it back. Whereas politics possesses a 鈥渇utural orientation,鈥 Gandhi鈥檚 philosophy focuses on the 鈥渢actile immediacy of the instant鈥 (136) Reference to an ideal future characterizes political thought. The refusal to make such reference distinguishes Gandhi, in Mehta鈥檚 view, as an uncompromisingly anti-political thinker (149, 151).
In diametric opposition to political tactics, nonviolent demonstrations fulfill the yearning for freedom immediately. Such freedom was, in Gandhi鈥檚 view, the only kind worthy of the name since it was not just immediate but also 鈥渨ithin the reach of anyone who desired it, no matter how powerless or oppressed.鈥[17] Its sole requirement is that one fearlessly accept the possibility of one鈥檚 own slaughter, the precondition of not cooperating with an unjust order.聽Gandhi鈥檚 anti-politics of nonviolence effectively re-institute the equality before death politics was originally intended to banish.
In Weil as well, one鈥檚 capacity for nonviolence is inseparable from one鈥檚 willingness to expose oneself to violence. The violence in question for Weil is what she calls 鈥渇orce鈥: the power that will, inevitably, transfigure all human beings, turning them into 鈥渘onentit[ies]鈥 or 鈥渋nert matter.鈥[18] In Weil鈥檚 essay on the Illiad, the warriors attempt to deliver themselves from force鈥 whether the trauma of being subjected to it during their lives or the terror of being subdued by it in the end鈥攂y wielding it themselves, assuming the role of mythic gods who turn their adversaries into 鈥渂easts or objects鈥 (65). Like politics in Gandhi鈥檚 schema, force turns its victims into means rather than ends, thus reinforcing the 鈥渟uperstition[s] of chronology鈥 and 鈥減rogress.鈥[19]
According to Weil, one escapes this dynamic only by immersing oneself in the 鈥渁nguish鈥 of a body that has been or will be transformed by force. Her premise is that one will value the other鈥檚 life more than force only when one is not concerned to prolong one鈥檚 own life above all. Hence, like ahimsa in Gandhi鈥檚 thought, the terms Weil uses to name this practice of immersion鈥攕uch as 鈥渁ttention,鈥 鈥渄ecreation,鈥 鈥減assive activity,鈥 鈥渘on-active action,鈥 or 鈥渘egative effort鈥濃攅mphasize its lack of anxiety about the future.[20] Referring to the Illiad鈥檚 characters, she observes: 鈥淎ll who escape the empire of force in their innermost being and in their relations with their fellow men are loved, but loved in grief at the threat of constantly impending destruction鈥 (66).
Though Cr茅pon buttresses his argument with Butler, her thought has more in common with Gandhi鈥檚 and Weil鈥檚 disavowal of security than his own desire to globalize it. In fact, Frames of War explicitly argues that the 鈥済round鈥 of nonviolence is the acceptance of insecurity as a global fact, not the effort to turn security into such: 鈥渘onviolence is derived from the apprehension of equality in the midst of precariousness鈥 (181, 183). If 鈥減olitics鈥 in Arendt鈥檚 sense provides an 鈥渆scape from the equality before death,鈥 nonviolent praxes, in Butler鈥檚 view, abides by precisely this equality. Precarious Life asks: 鈥淗ow does a collective deal 鈥 with its vulnerability to violence? [A]t whose expense, does it gain a purchase on 鈥渟ecurity鈥濃?[21] In the same vein: 鈥渢o make ourselves secure at the expense of every other human consideration is to eradicate [鈥渢he sense of human vulnerability鈥漖, one of [our] most important resources鈥 (30). Cr茅pon suggests that every outbreak of insecurity demands immediate action. Butler argues, in contrast, that such reactivity is trapped within the circle of murderous consent.
According to Martel鈥檚 鈥淔oreword,鈥 Murderous Consent will 鈥渞uffle鈥 the 鈥渇eathers鈥 of 鈥渢he Fanonian postcolonial studies world[,] who see violence as both necessary and valid as such鈥 (x). I doubt this 鈥渨orld鈥濃攚hose scholars, according to Martel, 鈥渙penly espouse violence鈥濃攅xists outside the liberal academic imagination, always desperate for postcolonial straw figures. Fanon鈥檚 own discussions of violence are, in fact, much more nuanced than Cr茅pon鈥檚. The Wretched of the Earth emphasizes that colonial violence reflects the settlers鈥 鈥減reoccupation with security.鈥[22] Fanon鈥檚 1960 lecture in Accra addressed Kwame Nkrumah, who had abjured anticolonial violence. Here, in contrast to Cr茅pon or Camus, Fanon carefully distinguished between forms of violence. He invoked the 1945 anticolonial protests in S茅tif and Guelma, after which a reported 45,000 Algerians were killed鈥攊n order 鈥渢o destroy,鈥 in de Gaulle鈥檚 words, 鈥渁ny idea of the Algerian nation鈥.[23] The massacres instead gave rise, in Fanon鈥檚 view, to an antithetical nation, one that responded dialectically to colonial violence.
Fanon emphasized that, by the time Algerians rose up in arms (a decade after S茅tif and Guelma), they had lost all concern for their own security: 鈥渢he achievement of the Algerian revolution is precisely 鈥 to have caused a mutation of the instinct of self-preservation into value and truth鈥 (655). In other words, the revolutionaries considered even more precious than their safety their freedom to live according to their own principles. Fanon considered anticolonial violence, originally, a sacrificial act, 鈥渢he last gesture of the hunted man鈥 who 鈥渘o longer鈥 can give 鈥渁 meaning to his life鈥 so instead gives 鈥渙ne to his death.鈥 Such violence disseminates a literally post-colonial form of consciousness, founded not on security but, conversely, on the embrace of mortality. This consciousness is, in turn, a new basis for transnational solidarity: 鈥渢he valiant Yugoslav people [welcome] Algerian amputees, dismembered, blinded鈥; 鈥淓uropeans from Algeria, descendants of settlers 鈥 die under French bullets in the ranks of the valiant National Liberation Army鈥 (658). For Fanon, as for Gandhi and Weil, the alternative to political violence is not a nonviolent polity鈥攏o such contradiction in terms. If politics is constitutively violent, one can resist political violence only by ceaselessly exposing oneself to it.
Cr茅pon claims that such sacrificial acts 鈥渆fface鈥 life鈥檚 value (33, 145). In fact, he blames less security measures than 鈥渢he eulogists of heroic death鈥 for propagating murderous consent (33). He thus makes the willingness to sacrifice oneself for one鈥檚 principles another version, merely, of political violence. Yet this willingness marks every genuine project to oppose political violence, as we have seen in Gandhi鈥檚 and Weil鈥檚 practice of nonviolence, on one hand, and Fanon鈥檚 discussion of anticolonial violence, on the other. One could argue that it recurs around the world today鈥攏ot only in peaceful demonstrations against neoliberal policies and/or police brutality, whose participants know only too well the risk involved, but, more controversially, in suicide bombing. In every case, action, armed or not, demands that one disavow the prototypically political principle of security, of 鈥渟eek[ing] only life and not death.鈥
This disavowal was fundamental, finally, to the ethics Foucault explored in his last years.聽He modeled it on the Athenian concept of parrhesia (or 鈥渇earless speech鈥), whose protocols demand one speak one鈥檚 mind freely to those with more power than oneself: 鈥淸one] risk[s] death to tell the truth instead of reposing in the security of a life where the truth goes unspoken.鈥[24] Only by taking this risk can one, in Foucault鈥檚 words, call 鈥渋nto question domination at every level and in every form in which it exists.鈥[25] One acts ethically, in short, when one treats as sacred not life but rather the right to live according to one鈥檚 own truth, a right for which one must be ready to sacrifice one鈥檚 life. 鈥淚 dream of the intellectual,鈥 Foucault said, 鈥渨ho [questions] whether the revolution is worth the trouble[,] it being understood that the question can be answered only by those who are willing to risk their lives to bring it about.鈥[26] In their willingness to die for their principles, Foucault鈥檚 ideal intellectuals choose the path not of politics but rather of all those who have suffered its violence.
In his late works, Foucault named the 鈥減rice鈥 one pays for truth 鈥渟pirituality.鈥[27] In the same year he lectured on raison d鈥櫭塼at, he reflected on the 1967-68 anti-government protests he had witnessed in Tunisia more than a decade before and the 1978 Iranian Revolution he also observed firsthand. In regard to the former, he asked: 鈥渨hat can prompt in an individual the desire 鈥 for absolute sacrifice, without 鈥 the least ambition 鈥 for power and profit? 鈥 I saw in Tunisia, the evidence of 鈥 spirituality, the unbearable quality of certain situations produced by capitalism, colonialism, and neocolonialism.鈥[28] And in regard to the Iranian Revolution (before it was co-opted by 鈥渢he bloody government of an integrist clergy鈥), Foucault wrote: 鈥渨hat is the point of searching, even at the cost their own lives, for this thing whose possibility we [Europeans] have forgotten since the Renaissance and the great crises of Christianity: a political spirituality? I can already hear the French laughing, but I know they are wrong.鈥[29] Secular intellectuals deride Foucault鈥檚 support for the revolution still today. This derision reflects their fear of the perilous freedom that accompanies spirituality in Foucault鈥檚 sense鈥攁 type of freedom that, four centuries ago, nascent Western states replaced with a fixation on extending life. Only those who face this fear have a chance of finding their way to nonviolence.
Siraj Ahmed is Professor of English at the CUNY Graduate Center and of English and Comparative Literature at Lehman College. He is the author of Archaeology of Babel: The Colonial Foundation of the Humanities (Stanford, 2018; MLA Scaglione Prize for Comparative Literary Studies); The Stillbirth of Capital: Enlightenment Writing and Colonial India (Stanford, 2012); and essays in Critical Inquiry, Representations, Cultural Critique, Postcolonial Studies, The Immanent Frame, the Blackwell Companion to Literary Theory, and The Postcolonial Enlightenment, among other journals and edited collections.
References:
[1] Marc Cr茅pon, Murderous Consent: On the Accommodation of Violent Death (Fordham, 2019), 17-8. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[2] James Martel, 鈥淔oreword鈥 in Cr茅pon op. cit., ix-xiii, x. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[3] Judith Butler, Frames of War: When is Life Grievable (Verso, 2009), 178. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[4] Adi Ophir, 鈥淭he Politics of Catastrophization: Emergency and Exception,鈥 in Didier Fassin and Mariella Pandolfi, eds, Contemporary States of Emergency: The Politics of Military and Humanitarian Interventions (Zone, 2013), 59-88, 64, 79. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[5] Mariella Pandolfi, 鈥淔rom Paradox to Paradigm: The Permanent State of Emergency in the Balkans鈥 in Fassin and Pandolfi op. cit., 153-72, 165.
[6] Didier Fassin and Mariella Pandolfi, 鈥淚ntroduction: Military and Humanitarian Government in the Age of Intervention鈥 in Fassin and Pandolfi op. cit., 9-25, 16. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[7] Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (Harcourt, 1968), 267-302, esp. 272, 291, 299 and On Revolution, (Penguin, 1990), 149.
[8] Faisal Devji, The Impossible Indian: Gandhi and the Temptation of Violence (Harvard, 2012), 186.
[9] M. K. Gandhi, The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi (Publications Division Government of India, 1976), 65:361; Devji, 185.
[10] Devji, 186.
[11] Hannah Arendt, Crisis of the Republic (Harcourt, 1972), 165. The quotation that follows is from the same page.
[12] Michel Foucault, Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the Coll猫ge de France 1977-1978 (Palgrave, 2009). 286. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[13] Mark Duffield, Development, Security and Unending War: Governing the World of Peoples (Polity, 2007).
[14] Pandolfi, 166. The quotation that follows is from the same page.
[15] Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (University of Chicago, 2007), 29.
[16] Uday Mehta, 鈥淕andhi and the Common Logic of War and Peace,鈥 Raritan 30.1 (Summer 2010), 134-56, 141. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[17] Devji, 93-94.
[18] James Holoka, ed., Simone Weil鈥榮 The Iliad, Or, The Poem of Force: A Critical Edition (Peter Lang, 2003), 48, 50, 61, 66, 71. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[19] Simone Weil, Letter to a Priest (Routledge, 2002), 29.
[20] Simone Weil, Waiting for God (HarperCollins, 2009), 61, 126 and The Notebooks of Simone Weil (Putnam鈥檚 Sons, 1956), 124.
[21] Judith Butler, Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence (Verso, 2006), 42. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[22] Frantz Fanon, The Wretched of the Earth (Grove, 1963), 53.
[23] Frantz Fanon, Alienation and Freedom (Bloomsbury, 2018), 657. Cited hereafter parenthetically in text.
[24] Michel Foucault, Fearless Speech (Semiotext(e), 2001), 13, 17.
[25] Michel Foucault, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth (New Press, 1997), 300.
[26] Michel Foucault, Politics, Philosophy, Culture: Interviews and Other Writings (Routledge, 1988), 124.
[27] Michel Foucault, The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Coll猫ge de France 1981-1982 (Palgrave, 2005), 15-6.
[28] Michel Foucault, Power (New Press, 2000), 280.
[29] Ibid., 451; Michel Foucault, 鈥淲hat are the Iranians Dreaming 今日看料?鈥 in Janet Afary and Kevin Anderson, Foucault and the Iranian Revolution: Gender and the Seductions of Islamism (University of Chicago, 2005), 203-9, 209.
Photo: The writer during the moment of creative inspiration. Illustration by Eugene Ivanov | Shutterstock
Published on August 4, 2020.