This is part of a roundtable on Marc Cr茅pon鈥檚 Murderous Consent: On the Accommodation of Violent Death.
There are few words in our contemporary public discourse so fraught, so politically incendiary, and so persistently challenged in meaning and usage as 鈥渃onsent.鈥 The traditional notion of consent involves rational agents who freely enter agreements based on a calculation of interests. Questions of ethical and legal responsibility are gauged by the consent of the involved parties, ascribing a contractarian model to scrutinize acceptable conduct. According to this view, consent and responsibility go hand in hand, and culpability derives from the violation of consent. However, claims of consent are also used to justify all sorts of violence. Marc Cr茅pon鈥檚 Murderous Consent: On the Accommodation of Violent Death provocatively suggests there is something rotten at the core of consent itself. The notion of 鈥渕urderous consent鈥 turns the ordinary concept on its head, revealing its underside where one does not consent by what one does or says, but rather through accommodation, passivity, inaction, and the failure to speak up in the face of injustice and violence. Through his readings of literary and philosophical texts, Cr茅pon explores how murderous consent inoculates itself against criticism, and anesthetizes individuals from ethical reasonability by occluding or accommodating violence. The breakdown of consent begins at the level of language itself, where murderous consent takes root in the ambivalence and insufficiency of our words condemning violence. Translating Murderous Consent therefore demanded an acute sensitivity to the fragility of words that are so easily coopted to serve violence.
Murderous consent functions by dividing and separating individuals from the unseen or far away consequences of their actions, producing 鈥渁 fault or rift in our being-in-the-world.鈥[1] Cr茅pon often employs the geological language of 鈥渞uptures,鈥 [ruptures] 鈥渞ifts,鈥 [产谤猫肠丑别蝉] 鈥渇ractures,鈥 [brisures] 鈥渇aults,鈥 [failles] and 鈥渃hasms鈥 [gouffres] to describe the effects of murderous consent. These cracks between individuals and the world they inhabit illustrate a breakdown in ethical responsibility generated by the nefarious side of consent, which is on display in a host of contemporary political debates. The 鈥渃onsent of the governed鈥 has long served as a guiding principle of representative governance, symbolized by the mythical 鈥渟ocial contract鈥 that grants the sovereign the monopoly on the legitimate use of force in exchange for a guarantee of citizens鈥 security and basic rights. We may wonder if this hypothetical contract is even operative in contemporary politics. Today, maintaining citizens鈥 consent is not used as a threat of revolt against an unresponsive tyrant, but more often as a cudgel to antagonize or suppress critics.[2] 听In the United States, considering the hundreds of thousands of people brought to the country in bondage against their will, and the millions that have endured over four hundred years of chattel slavery and systematic racial oppression, the notion that the state maintains its legitimacy through the consent of the governed has always been a deeply injurious fiction.
Consent is at the core of so many questions in contemporary politics. The #MeToo Movement has revealed the terrifyingly widespread disrespect of sexual consent hiding in plain sight in practically every aspect of society. Aggressors often resort to 鈥渋mplied鈥 consent to justify misdeeds: when a woman鈥檚 appearance or clothing is used to argue 鈥渟he was asking for it,鈥 the essence of this justification for rape is an assertion of consent. In so many cases, survivors of sexual violence struggle to receive justice through the courts because, amongst other reasons, their accounts of non-consent are doubted. The ambiguous territory of 鈥渋mplied鈥 consent is routinely used to blur the distinction between act and omission, and ultimately to excuse sexual violence. Muddling the limits of consent is an effective strategy for obscuring responsibility for all sorts of violations. Personal data collection on the internet has introduced a new frontier in debates over passive consent. Users regularly agree to the terms of use for digital platforms and services without reading what information they have consent to release; with the ease of a click, internet users nominally consent to massive violations of their privacy. But granting nominal consent does little to curb its manifold abuses. The staggering extent of personal data collection by companies such as Google or Facebook not only enables them to monetize this information to target consumer habits, it also allows them to weaponized this data to shape political opinion and manufacture consent. The cracks that emerge suggest a deeper problem with the notion of consent itself.
The formulation 鈥渕urderous consent鈥 is striking because it confronts us with an uncomfortable truth: while most of us would not actively consent to murder, just as we would prefer to think that we do not condone violence, we are all participants in a range of systems of violence which we generally accept with resignation, passivity, and silence. Murderous consent is the operating principle of the modern state, which on principle it must vigorously deny for its own legitimation. Marc Cr茅pon defines murderous consent as 鈥渁ny accommodation with violent death, any habituation to murder, any compromise, in reality untenable, with principles [鈥 that should forbid even the slightest exception, regardless of who the victims are.鈥[3] Cr茅pon proposes a thoroughgoing critique of violence, equally applicable to the revolution as the counter-revolution, without accommodation for murder, whether it takes place here or far away, without distinctions based on nationality, race, religion, gender, sexuality, or other distinguishing factors. Murderous Consentexplores the ways that consent is imbricated in systems of violence鈥攁ctively or passively, consciously or unwittingly鈥攁nd how it is used to occlude ethical responsibility. In the United States, the massive protest movement for racial justice sparked by the police killing of George Floyd has underscored the urgent need to respond to the institutionalized violence perpetrated mainly against impoverished people of color, and it has laid bare the widespread complicity particularly of white people through inaction and silence. Excusing police violence committed in the name of 鈥渓aw and order鈥 is a quintessential tactic of murderous consent.
The forms of murderous consent are so extensive and deeply rooted that there is inevitably a temptation to throw up our hands, and resign ourselves to accepting the inevitability of violence. We are all adept at finding excuses for inaction, whether by moral accommodation, utilitarian calculation, or simply by choosing to look away.[4] Murderous consent is, Cr茅pon writes, 鈥渟trengthened by resignation and a fatalistic 鈥榓cquiescence.鈥欌[5] This is the specter of what he defines as nihilism, which is the ultimate weapon of murderous consent: 鈥渄oing nothing, saying nothing, or refusing all feelings, because nothing will ever change [鈥 is always to consent to murder a little bit.鈥[6] Murderous consent is the normalization of acceptable forms of violence as unfortunate but inevitable; it is assuaging our guilt for civilian casualties of war by referring to them as 鈥渃ollateral damage鈥; it is shielding police officers from accountability for heinous acts of misconduct committed in a different neighborhood; it is discounting any form of violence because it takes place far away 鈥 whether in a far-off country or even within one鈥檚 own country鈥攐r because its victims are of a different race, religion, nationality, or gender.[7] The contractarian notion of consent proves utterly insufficient to respond to the ethical injunction against violence, and incapable of asserting what Cr茅pon calls 鈥渆thicosmopolitics.鈥
The ineradicable quality of murderous consent highlights a phenomenon that Jacques Derrida calls 鈥渁utoimmunity.鈥 Cr茅pon only refers to this notion once in Murderous Consent, but the logic of autoimmunity explains the stubborn persistence of murderous consent against attempts to wrestle it under the control of a law or principle. The notion of autoimmunity draws a parallel with the biological pathology in which the body fails to distinguish between its own antibodies and foreign antigens, causing the immune system to react to protect the body by attacking the body. Derrida suggests that a similar logic of the autoimmune response is at work in the organization of human societies. In 鈥淔aith and Knowledge鈥 he writes, 鈥渢he autoimmunitary [濒鈥檃耻迟辞颈尘尘耻苍颈迟补颈谤别] haunts the community and its system of immunitary survival like the hyperbole of its own possibility. Nothing in common, nothing immune, safe and sound, heilig and holy, nothing unscathed in the most autonomous living present without a risk of autoimmunity.鈥[8] To protect the body politic against itself, a community will neutralize threats to its legitimation by any means necessary, even if this means attacking its own members. Derrida emphasizes, 鈥渘o community <is possible> that would not cultivate its own autoimmunity, a principle of sacrificial self-destruction ruining the principle of self-protection,鈥 in the name of 鈥渟ome sort of invisible and spectral sur-vival.鈥[9] The autoimmune response of a society to eradicate threats from within illustrates the breakdown of consent. Even when it is supposed to codify legal standards for what is permissible for individuals and states, consent is always prone to turn against itself, to violate its own terms of use, and to sacrifice those under its protection. By developing ever more insidious ways of justifying violence by occulting responsibility, murderous consent illustrates the logic of autoimmunity: it deflects criticism by violating consent in the name of consent, and it insists on the recourse to violence to protect against threats, real or supposed, in the name of some higher ideal. The sacrificial logic of murderous consent undercuts every attempt at a systematic critique of violence.
If, indeed, the state鈥檚 legitimacy derives from the consent of the governed, then citizens should be responsibility for violence the state commits in their name. Representative government can enact laws, treaties, and agreements that are intended to codify and restrict its violent excesses, but the autoimmunity of sovereignty is precisely the possibility that the state breaks its contractual agreements, violates its principles, and declares a 鈥渟tate of exception鈥 to justify violence. Sovereignty cannot tolerate a law that limits its own sovereignty: to subject the state to rules that limit its authority is, Derrida explains in Rogues, 鈥渢o turn sovereignty against itself, to compromise its immunity.鈥[10] To inoculate itself against threats to its legitimacy and reassert its exceptional hold on power, the state can break its own rules, usurp its self-imposed limitations, and justify violence based on the tacit consent of the people. 鈥淧ure sovereignty does not exist,鈥 Derrida writes, 鈥渋t is always in the process of positing itself by refuting itself, by denying or disavowing itself; it is always in the process of autoimmunizing itself, of betraying itself by betraying the democracy that nonetheless can never do without it.鈥[11] The paradox is that sovereign power reaffirms its legitimacy by asserting the possibility to commit violence, while it simultaneously denies its own sovereignty by justifying its actions based on the consent of the governed. This autoimmune response protects sovereignty from criticism. To affirm the principle of the consent of the governed is already to enable the system of murderous consent: 鈥淎s soon as there is sovereignty, there is abuse of power and a rogue state. Abuse is the law of use; it is the law itself, the “logic” of a sovereignty that can reign only by not sharing.鈥[12] It is impossible to disentangle the operation of sovereignty from the abuse of its power because it is precisely in this way that sovereignty reaffirms its grip. Similarly, amidst the growing criticism of police tactics and enforcement, the failed history of police 鈥渞eform鈥 offers an instructive example of the auto-immune response: by making big promises and delivering half-measures, previous reforms have only inoculated the police against threats to their entrenched power.
Autoimmunity begins at the level of language itself. The words and euphemisms used to describe the victims of violence allow individuals to set aside their own complicity and responsibility. 鈥淓verything begins with naming,鈥[13] Cr茅pon writes, 鈥淲hat state do we call a 鈥榬ogue鈥 state? What states are we forbidden from calling rogue states? Who or what will we allow ourselves to characterize as 鈥榗ruel鈥 or 鈥榖arbarian鈥?鈥 [14] By the same token, those who misrepresent today鈥檚 protesters as 鈥渞ioters,鈥 鈥渓ooters,鈥 and 鈥渢hugs鈥 also use naming to antagonize and discredit their opponents. The rhetoric of friend-enemy distinctions expresses conflicts in the reductive terms of civilization versus barbarism, freedom versus totalitarianism, or democracy versus tyranny. These Manichean oppositions insulate the state from criticism, and they depict the enemy as somehow less human and less deserving of ethical treatment. For Cr茅pon, naming is a crucial technique of murderous consent for dividing blame and occluding responsibility: 鈥渘aming lets us shut our eyes and ears,鈥 naming establishes 鈥渁 separation, however unjustifiable, between those who we think should be protected against violence by whatever means necessary and those for whom the violence they might experience is not considered an issue of basic principle.鈥[15] Euphemism becomes a weapon to distance and abstract from the victims of violence. For the same reason, when protesters demand 鈥淪ay their names,鈥 and repeat the full names of victims of police violence, it is to insist on the humanity of the victims as individuals, and the gravity of each loss.
Murderous consent operates by corrupting the language of justice, freedom, and democracy with violence. In his breathtaking reading of G眉nter Anders鈥 reflections on the atomic age, Cr茅pon identifies the autoimmunity on display in the language of nuclear deterrence. Defenders of nuclear deterrence construct a binary choice between 鈥渢otalitarianism or freedom,鈥 and claim that only the possession of nuclear weapons鈥攁nd the threat of their use鈥攌eeps us free from totalitarianism. But Anders keenly observes that no democracy could survive a nuclear exchange, much less remain democratic in its aftermath. According to the logic of deterrence, free nations must possess nuclear weapons to protect themselves from those who threaten freedom, even if freedom itself could not survive a nuclear war. 鈥淭he 鈥榝ree world鈥 is one whose freedom is conditioned by threat,鈥[16] Cr茅pon writes. The logic of nuclear deterrence is perhaps the ultimate case of murderous consent: the forced choice between 鈥渢otalitarianism or freedom鈥 implies the possession of nuclear weapons for the sake of deterrence, but even the hypothetical threat of a nuclear attack as deterrence is an embrace of murderous consent. Only a few powerful people could decide to launch a nuclear attack, but their decisions would have ramifications for all of humanity. Nothing could be less emblematic of the 鈥渇ree world.鈥 Murderous consent appropriates our highest ideals as a cover for violence, turning the meaning of words against themselves.
Marc Cr茅pon鈥檚 prose explores the intricacies, ambivalences, and contradictions of concepts such as consent, freedom, and violence. No ideal is safe from corruption by murderous consent. The autoimmunity of murderous consent is expressed in its uncanny ability to turn words against themselves, to paradoxically violate consent for the sake of preserving consent. A difficult aspect of translating Murderous Consent concerned the frequent use of 鈥淛anus words,鈥 words that express a certain meaning as well as its opposite. Just as consent can validate ethical behavior or accommodate violence, Cr茅pon frequently invokes notions that exhibit this doubled-edged quality, including 鈥渃omplicity鈥 [complicit茅, complice, communaut茅 complice],鈥 鈥渃ompromise鈥 [compromis, compromission] 鈥渃ollaboration,鈥 鈥(de)-solidarization,鈥 and even 鈥渇raternity.鈥 These notions can be deployed to invoke 鈥渆thicosmopolitics,鈥 but they are also prone to being appropriated to justify exclusion or violence against the other. Camus speaks of 鈥渢he small part of existence that can be realized on this earth through the mutual complicity of men,鈥[17] but complicity can also describe the accommodation of injustice and silent complicity to violence by bystanders. 鈥淐ollaboration鈥 can suggest people working together for the improvement of humanity, but the French word carries the stink of the 鈥渃ollabo鈥 who aided the Nazis during the Second World War. 鈥淔raternity鈥 rather explicitly leaves out half of humanity. The positive or negative meanings of these words turn on the context of culturally specific historical signifiers. Cr茅pon demonstrates that even the loftiest ideals of freedom, justice, democracy, 鈥渢he people,鈥 or 鈥渢he nation鈥 are all too easily coopted to enable violence.[18]
鈥淭he way in which dreams treat the category of contraries and contradictories is highly remarkable,鈥 Freud observes in The Interpretation of Dreams, 鈥渋t is simply disregarded.鈥[19] Just as the ambivalent character of dreams is at once heimlich and unheimlich, the meaning of a word or thing in a dream can uncannily express both itself and its opposite. For Freud, this creates a difficulty for interpretation because 鈥渄reams feel themselves at liberty [鈥 to represent any element by its wishful contrary.鈥 The antonymic meaning of the words and symbols in dreams suggests an underlying connection between these opposing terms. He relates this observation to the linguistic phenomenon of 鈥減rimal words,鈥 which are words from early languages that mean both themselves and their opposites.[20] For Freud, these 鈥減rimal words鈥 confirm 鈥渢he regressive, archaic character of the expression of thoughts in dreams,鈥[21] as if the logic of the dream-work uncovers a deep-seated linguistic primitivism where antonyms remain undifferentiated. The language of Murderous Consent reflects the double-sided meaning of Freud鈥檚 鈥減rimal words:鈥 consent鈥檚 autoimmunity is precisely its capacity to justify non-consent. Murderous consent infiltrates our words with violence, and it sours our ideals with passive justifications for murder鈥攅ven where consent is supposed to insulate us from this risk. Indeed, murderous consent lulls us into a certain kind of dream where consent and non-consent recede into non-distinction. As Cr茅pon describes the fate of the title character in Camus鈥 Caligula at the end of his bloody reign, 鈥渁ll that is left of his dream of justice is the mirror image that is violence. Ultimately, having pursued his dream to the ends of the Earth, he finds only a distorted image of his own freedom鈥攏either the world nor justice.鈥[22] Facilitated by murderous consent, Caligula鈥檚 dream of justice is unmasked as nothing but a fa莽ade for violence. Snapping out of the dream and awakening to the violence discreetly justified by murderous consent demands that we reevaluate the notion of consent with clear eyes. This is the great merit of Marc Cr茅pon鈥檚 Murderous Consent, and the difficult task for his translators.
听
Jacob Levi is a Ph.D candidate in the Department of Comparative Thought and Literature at Johns Hopkins University, and a graduate of the 脡cole Normale Sup茅rieure. He is currently in the final stages of his doctoral dissertation on Jewish intellectuals in Paris during the 1960s, entitled 鈥淭he Adventure of the Book: Jab猫s, Derrida, Levinas.鈥
References:
[1] Marc Cr茅pon, Murderous Consent: On the Accommodation of Violent Death, (New York: Fordham University Press, 2019), 25.
[2] When the current president of the United States told four congresswomen of color in the summer of 2019 to 鈥済o back听[to the] places from which听they came,鈥 and 鈥渋f you don鈥檛 like it here, you can leave,鈥 he ostensibly invoked the logic of consent to summon the ethno-nationalistic conception of the state, based on the connection between blood and soil. The comments clearly imply that criticism of the president 鈥 especially from women of color 鈥 is tantamount to a breach of loyalty to the state.
[3] Cr茅pon, 2.
[4] A popular slogan at recent protests in the United States following the police murder of George Floyd has been 鈥渨hite silence equals violence.鈥 This succinct expression of murderous consent illustrates that it does not require active participation in police violence to be complicit in the systematic oppression of Black people in the United States, of which police violence is only the most visible and brutal symptom. The slogan reveals that, particularly for white people, merely remaining silent and doing nothing in the face of such staggering injustice is tantamount to complicity. This is what Martin Luther King Jr. described in the 鈥淟etter from a Birmingham Jail鈥 as the problem of the 鈥渨hite moderate,鈥 who is 鈥渕ore devoted to 鈥榦rder鈥 than to justice,鈥 who 鈥減refers a negative peace which is the absence of tension to a positive peace which is the presence of justice.鈥 The Black Lives Matter protest movement has highlighted the inadequacy of the well-intentioned liberal who is content to merely claim that he or she is 鈥渘ot racist,鈥 and instead the movement calls for more proactive forms of 鈥渁nti-racism鈥 that contribute to dismantling systemic injustice and institutionalized forms of white supremacy. Confronting silent complicity is a key tool for uprooting the mechanisms of murderous consent.
[5] Cr茅pon, 3.
[6] Ibid, 3-4.
[7] The expressions of moral accommodation by those who engineer and support these policies are often couched in the language of consent. Innocent victims of drone strikes are casually blamed for their own deaths because they should have known not to be at the same wedding or restaurant as known terrorists. Europeans can wash their hands of responsibility for the 鈥渆conomic migrants鈥 who die in shoddy boats crossing the Mediterranean Sea, because they knew the risks they were taking. The United States can pass off separating Central American children from their parents and putting them in squalid prisons because they broke the law by entering the country illegally. Victim blaming is endemic to murderous consent.
[8] Jacques Derrida, 鈥淔aith and Knowledge: Two Sources of 鈥楻eligion at the Limits of Reason Alone,鈥 Acts of Religion, (New York: Routledge, 2002), 82.
[9] Ibid, 87.
[10] Derrida, Rogues: Two Essays on Reason, (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005), 101.
[11] Ibid, 101.
[12] Ibid, 102.
[13] Cr茅pon, 117.
[14] Ibid, 118.
[15] Ibid, 122-123.
[16] Ibid, 144.
[17] Ibid, 27.
[18] When Steve Bannon described the Trump administration鈥檚 task in 2017 as the 鈥渄econstruction of the administrative state,鈥 a thinly veiled declaration of his white nationalist agenda, he sought to coopt the leftist notion of deconstruction as a tool for subverting power, disrupting hierarchies, and seeking liberation. Whether intentional or not, Bannon鈥檚 comment inverts Derrida鈥檚 position in 鈥淔orce of Law鈥 where he argues that 鈥deconstruction is justice,鈥 and his insistence 鈥 contra Bannon鈥檚 regressive ideological views 鈥 on the 鈥渦ndeconstructability of justice鈥 (Derrida, 鈥淔orce of Law鈥 in Acts of Religion, 243).
[19] Sigmund Freud, The Interpretation of Dreams in Standard Edition, vol. 4, (London: Hogarth Press, 1953), 318.
[20] In a short 1910 piece entitled 鈥淭he Antithetical Meaning of Primal Words,鈥 Freud discusses Karl Abel鈥檚 philological evidence that ancient Egyptian featured certain 鈥減rimal words.鈥 Freud suggests that traces of this phenomenon are even visible in the Latin terms sacer, which means both sacred and cursed, or altus, which means both high and deep, and even the highly antonymic English word, 鈥渨ithout.鈥
[21] Freud, 鈥淭he Antithetical Meaning of Primal Words,鈥 in Standard Edition, vol. 11, 161.
[22] Cr茅pon, 20.
Photo: Travel in the big fish
Published on August 4, 2020.